Session Information
13 SES 04 B, Language, Concepts and Translation
Paper Session
Contribution
Introduction
Whether making claims of logical superiority, of the holiness of a particular language, or striving to be sure that ‘proper’ language use is maintained, one is engaged in attitudes and practices that are firmly grounded in the ideology of ‘linguistic legitimacy’. The core idea at the heart of this ideology is that particular languages or language varieties are innately superior in some fundamental way to others. There are multiple settings in which linguistic legitimacy occurs: in everyday social discourse, in educational institutions, in politics and political discourse, and in scholarly settings. It is not only factually wrong in all of these contexts, it is also potentionally destructive and oppressive. Nevertheless, it is incredibly common in all of these contexts, and most of us – even those of us who should know better -- are susceptible to it from time to time. This presentation will involve an in-depth philosophical analysis of the concept of ‘linguistic legitimacy’, including the related concepts ‘language’, ‘language variety’ and ‘language purism’. This conceptual analysis of ‘linguistic legitimacy’ will then be applied to a number of contemporary examples, including the case of Romani, the signed languages used by the Deaf, Esperanto and other international auxiliary languages, and an historical example, the perceptions of Yiddish during the pre-World War II period, especially in Germany and Eastern Europe.
Research Questions
The basic research questions to be addressed in this presentation are: (1) What is ‘linguistic legitimacy’? (2) How is ‘linguistic legitimacy’ manifested in the case of a number of selected languages in varying social and educational settings? and (3) Insofar as ‘linguistic legitimacy’ can be considered to be an ideology, what risks are associated with it from social and educational perspectives?
Conceptual Framework
The concept ‘linguistic legitimacy’ is both a timely and important one for educators, since it entails issues of social class, ethnicity, and culture, as well as being embedded in relations of dominance and power. ‘Linguistic legitimacy’ as a construct is also important with respect to the implications that it has for the development and implementation of educational policy, as numerous educational controversies around the world attest. The conceptual analysis to be offered in this presentation will entail the nature and history of the concept ‘linguistic legitimacy’, and the conditions under which it can be said to be present in policy and pedagogical practice.
Following the conceptual analysis of ‘linguistic legitimacy’, examples of how this ideology functions in discourse about a number of special languages will be discussed. The first to be examined will be that of Romani, and common in-group and out-group attitudes and beliefs. The rejection of the signed languages used by the deaf will be explored, and a comparison will be drawn between the British and Scandinavian approaches to the use and legal status of signed languages. Next, attitudes and beliefs about the linguistic legitimacy and reality of artificially constructed such as Esperanto will be considered. Finally, the historical case of Yiddish, which was commonly rejected as ‘jargon’ rather than a real language in the pre-World War II era, will be briefly examined.
Once the conceptual analysis and examination of various examples of ‘linguistic legitimacy’ have been explored, a brief counter-argument will be presented, suggesting the serious social and educational harm that such an ideology can result in are unacceptable on both linguistic and educational grounds.
Method
Expected Outcomes
References
Aspin, D. (1995). Logical empiricism, post-empiricism and education. In P. Higgs (ed.), Metatheories in philosophy of education (pp. 21-49). Johannesburg: Heinemann. Bernstein, R. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism: Science, hermeneutics and praxis. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Coombs, J., & Daniels, L. (1991). Philosophical inquiry: Conceptual analysis. In E. Short (ed.), Forms of curriculum inquiry (pp. 27-41). Albany: State University of New York Press. Dearden, R., Hirst, P., & Peters, R. S. (Eds.). (1972a). Education and the development of reason, Part 1: A critique of current educational aims. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Dearden, R., Hirst, P., & Peters, R. S. (Eds.). (1972b). Education and the development of reason, Part 2: Reason. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Dearden, R., Hirst, P., & Peters, R. S. (Eds.). (1972c). Education and the development of reason, Part 3: Education and reason. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Hirst, P. (1973). Liberal education and the nature of knowledge. In R. S. Peters (ed.), The Philosophy of education (pp. 87-111). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hirst, P. (1993). Education, knowledge and practices. In R. Barrow & P. White (eds.), Beyond liberal education (pp. 184-199). London: Routledge. Hirst, P., & Peters, R. S. (1970). The logic of education. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Noddings, N. (1995). Philosophy of education. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Peters, R. S. (Ed.). (1973a). The concept of education. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Peters, R. S. (Ed.). (1973b). The philosophy of education. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Soltis, J. (1978). An introduction to the analysis of educational concept (2nd ed.). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Search the ECER Programme
- Search for keywords and phrases in "Text Search"
- Restrict in which part of the abstracts to search in "Where to search"
- Search for authors and in the respective field.
- For planning your conference attendance you may want to use the conference app, which will be issued some weeks before the conference
- If you are a session chair, best look up your chairing duties in the conference system (Conftool) or the app.