Session Information
13 SES 04 A, Philosophy, Wonder, Rhetoric
Paper Session
Contribution
Educational programs of critical thinking has since the 1950s been advocated by the Critical thinking movement, a research field consisting of a number of (mostly American) educational theorists. The movement is central to the broader research domain of critical thinking; among the most well-known actors are Robert Ennis, Harvey Siegel, and Richard Paul. The Critical thinking movement seems to have been considerably successful in putting the alleged need for a specific form of critical thinking on the agenda for educational policy makers within and outside of the United States – every university or school today has to relate to questions of critical thinking. However, what is perhaps most salient about the program of critical thinking, having since the 1980s established itself as an all-embracing educational struggle, is a certain vagueness that makes instructions and discussions on the teaching of critical thinking peculiarly empty: a consensus statement made by forty-six “critical thinking experts” describes the critical thinker as “habitually inquisitive, well-informed, trustful of reason, open-minded, flexible, fair-minded in evaluation, honest in facing personal biases, prudent in making judgments, willing to reconsider, clear about issues, orderly in complex matters, diligent in seeking relevant information, reasonable in the selection of criteria, focused in inquiry, and persistent in seeking results which are as precise as the subject and the circumstances of inquiry permit” (Facione, 1990, p. 3). In this paper I investigate what historical development has led to what I describe as a semantic emptying of the concept of critical thinking.
The concept of critique is here viewed as practices resulting from different levels of reflexivity. According to French sociologist Luc Boltanski, critique can aim at different aspects of reality: whereas highly reflexive forms of critique “test” the necessity or desirability of currently existing institutions or practices as such, critique based on a lower level of reflexivity instead focuses on testing the claims made by the various agents and instances of reality (Boltanski, 2011, pp. 103–110). In the history of the contemporary critical thinking conception, the conceptions of the notion of critique can be categorized in three different ways: 1) Radical critique has the ambition of by putting established practices, institutions, or social orders to the test, destabilizing reality itself. Science can for this form of critique function as a means for positioning the subject outside of the object for critique. 2) Reformist critique focuses on the capability of particular practices and on the claims institutions make about themselves, and by being tested, these practices and institutions can optimize their way of functioning or presenting themselves. 3) Protective critique is “reactive” to the influences of institutions on the subject rather than initiating changes. This form of critique is a practice of skepticism towards any seductive messages, and has the function of shielding the subject from ideologies and politics. The present historical investigation of the notion of critical thinking is guided by the dialectic between these different forms as modes of reflexivity.
Method
Expected Outcomes
References
Beardsley, M. C. (1954). Practical logic. New York: Prentice-Hall. Black, M. (1946). Critical thinking : an introduction to logic and scientific method. New York, N.Y.: Prentice-Hall. Boltanski, L. (2011). On critique: a sociology of emancipation. Cambridge: Polity. Ennis, R. H. (1962). A Concept of Critical Thinking. Harvard Educational Review, 32(1), 81–111. Ennis, R. H. (1989). Critical Thinking and Subject Specificity: Clarification and Needed Research. Educational Researcher, 18(3), 4–10. https://doi.org/10.2307/1174885 Ennis, R. H. (1990). The Extent to Which Critical Thinking Is Subject-Specific: Further Clarification. Educational Researcher, 19(4), 13–16. https://doi.org/10.2307/1176383 Facione, P. A. (1990). Critical thinking: A statement of expert consensus for purposes of educational assessment and instruction. Committee of pre-college philosophy of the American philosophical association. Friedman, M. (2000). A parting of the ways : Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Chicago: Open Court. McPeck, J. E. (1981). Critical thinking and education. Oxford: Robertson. McPeck, J. E. (1990). Critical Thinking and Subject Specificity: A Reply To Ennis. ResearchGate, 19(4), 10–12. https://doi.org/10.3102/0013189X019004010 Reisch, G. A. (2005). How the Cold War transformed philosophy of science : to the icy slopes of logic. Cambridge ; Cambridge University Press. Scheffler, I. (1973). Reason and teaching. London. Siegel, H. (1988). Educating reason : rationality, critical thinking, and education. New York ; Routledge. Uebel, T. E. (1992). Overcoming Logical Positivism from Within: The Emergence of Neurath’s Naturalism in the Vienna Circle’s Protocol Sentence Debate. Rodopi. Uebel, T. E. (2001). Carnap and Neurath in exile: Can their disputes be resolved? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 211–220. https://doi.org/10.1080/02698590120059077
Search the ECER Programme
- Search for keywords and phrases in "Text Search"
- Restrict in which part of the abstracts to search in "Where to search"
- Search for authors and in the respective field.
- For planning your conference attendance you may want to use the conference app, which will be issued some weeks before the conference
- If you are a session chair, best look up your chairing duties in the conference system (Conftool) or the app.